THE NEW RADICALISM
Leopold Kohr
First published in Resurgence under
John Papworth's editorship in 1967
The question has frequently been asked: Is
radicalism dead? With the advent of the affluent society, which
the Labour Party's socialist reforms did so much to usher in,
have not all its aims been fulfilled? What can Labour still be
radical about?
Before one can answer the question, it is
necessary to have a clear picture of what radicalism really means.
Obviously it is an ideology urging change. But this would turn
everybody into a radical. For who does not want change? Life
itself is change - the change of seasons, of growth, of ageing,
of generations. What characterises a radical is that he desires
change at an accelerated pace. Hence the first criterium concerns
a question of mood, of temperament. A radical is impatient. He
wants change fast.
But so does a criminal anxious to kill a person
long before his time is up; does this make him a radical too?
There are quite a few who think so, and therefore reject all
radicalism on grounds of temperament alone. But temperament alone
is not the only element defining an ideology. It is also the
purpose that counts.
And the purpose of radicalism is not just
to bring about change fast, but to do so in order to improve
the human lot. The emphasis is on the human, not the social,
lot. Considering society's practically indefinite span of life,
no speed is needed to improve the social condition. Time's process
of evolution will take care of this in the same way as it has
taken care of the condition of ant and bee societies whose present
stage of social perfection it accomplished without the need of
radical assistance.
But it is different with the human condition
whose improvement must be accomplished within the brief span
of life available to the individual. While society can thus wait,
its citizens cannot. It is because of the latter that impatience
and speed are both necessary and justified.
This gives us two defining elements of radicalism:
impatient temperament, and a purpose benefiting the human person.
But while this excludes the criminal, it would
qualify the Archbishop of Canterbury as a radical - a high minded
reformer anxious both to improve the lot of individual man, and
to achieve the results fast enough to improve his condition as
long as he is still alive. Yet we know that the venerable clergyman
does not quite fit our image of a radical.
A third defining element is therefore necessary.
The non-radical reformer is continuously hampered by institutions
which, owing their origin in an outmoded social environment,
have long frozen all human relationships into patterns of customs
and law which resist change not because of conservative tradition
or evil intent but because of the rigidities inherent in the
structure of every established order. Yet, the non-radical accepts
all this because of his fondness for ancient trimmings to which
he sees no other alternative.
The radical, on the other hand, does not accept
it. In his effort to overcome the delaying effect of existing
institutions, he feels he must step outside the established order.
He becomes a revolutionary.
With this we have the three essential ingredients
that go into the make-up of a radical. His temperament is impatient
for change. His purpose is the improvement of the lot of individual
man. His method is revolution - the attempt to accomplish his
purpose through the use of tools beyond the reach of the established
system.
It is this last criterium that distinguishes
him from the well-meaning Archbishop who, though equally impatient
for improving the human condition, tries to achieve it within
the existing system.
But what distinguishes him from a fascist
or a communist?
Each of the two latter is impatient for change,
and each aims at bringing about this change by stepping outside
the established order, through revolution. Nevertheless they
too fail to qualify as true radicals. For though they fulfil
the requirements of the first and third criterium, they fall
short in the case of the second. They want improvement, but not
of man.
Their concern belongs to society as a whole.
In the interest of improving the stock, health, race, status,
productivity and power of an organism whose longevity makes it
practically imperishable anyway, they may sacrifice the short-
lived human being by the millions.
Rather than being the beneficiary, the individual
citizen becomes the victim of their grand design, undertaken
for the glory of a future he will not live to enjoy, and as oppressive
in its effect on the living as a prince building pyramids and
palaces. If he ventures to make reference to his own purposes,
he is called a traitor and liquidated.
This is why neither fascists nor communists,
neither Castros nor Francos, though revolutionaries and reformers
both, are true radicals. They hurry where there is no need to
hurry.
They reform, but the wrong condition. This
does not mean that the radical is insensitive to social reform.
On the contrary. But he considers it the means, not the end of
his aims. His end is the improvement not of the social but the
human lot. The only question still to be answered is: what is
exactly meant by improving the human lot?
Since the beginning of time, man's full enjoyment
of life has been jeopardized by one principal condition: lack
of freedom. This means that improvement as applied to the human
lot can have only one meaning: liberation.
The true radical is therefore a liberator.
His purpose is to bring freedom to the individual.
He is not interested in a free society. The
most tyrannical societies are free. For this reason, the freedom
of society may often be the very cause keeping the individual
in subjection. Rome was a free society. No other society could
impose its will on it. But what good did it do to Cicero whose
life it demanded as a sacrifice to its appetites? In our own
time Switzerland is a free society in the sense that it has no
sovereign above itself. But this of course also makes the Soviet
Union a free society, or Communist China, or Nazi Germany, or
Trujillo's Dominican Republic, Castro's Cuba, Franco's Spain,
Tito's Yugoslavia. What the radical is interested in is a society
of the free - a vastly different proposition. Improvement in
the radical sense means therefore not improvement in diet, health,
life expectancy. Every tyrant wants this for his soldiers; every
exploiter for his workers.
It means liberation - liberation from servitude;
liberation from tyranny, including the tyranny emanating from
society itself. A radical can be anti-social. He can never be
anti-human.
Since there are four types of circumstances
capable of depriving the individual of his freedom, radicalism
has in the course of history produced not one but four movements
of liberation.
The first and most ancient was directed against
religious superstition. The earliest radicals were therefore
religious liberators. Fiercely resisted by the established order
of priests, priest-kings, and god-kings, whose sinister power
as sole interpreters of the divine will they had to break before
they could liberate man from his terror of supernatural influences,
each of them - Socrates, Christ, the Apostles - had to step outside
the existing religious framework. Each was a revolutionary. And
the freedom they brought was the first of the great freedoms
that have helped man to realise his humanity; the freedom of
mind, the freedom of conscience, the freedom to have his own
identity, to be himself. Indeed by prying him loose from the
collective haze of his superstitious group in which he had up
till then been submerged like a diffuse image in a block of marble
before the arrival of the sculptor, the religious liberators
not only freed but created the individual. From now on his soul
was his own, and God in him, not in priest, king, or society.
However, having become conscious of himself,
man soon began to realise that, though his mind had been set
free, his person had not. He was a slave, a serf, a subordinate,
human as any other but without status, without equality, without
full dignity. The circumstance whose oppression he now felt most
was no longer his religious but his political environment.
The new representatives of radicalism, frequently
evolving out of religious radicalism, were therefore the political
liberators. From the Gracchi of ancient Rome to the Wilhelm Tells
of the Middle Ages and the Liberals of 19th century England,
they had as their object the dignity of full citizenship and
political equality for all.
To the freedom of the mind they wanted to
add the freedom of the human person. And again they had to step
outside the existing order committed as it was to hierarchy and
privilege.
To accomplish their aims, they replaced aristocracy
with democracy, monarchy with republic, or absolute monarchy
with constitutional monarchy. The change of system was not always
violent. But it was always fundamental and revolutionary.
As spiritual liberation resulted in the quest
for political freedom, political liberation now led to the quest
for economic freedom. For without the latter, the former would
have remained a vain achievement. The seemingly last mission
of radicalism was thus the economic liberation of man.
Again the main obstacle lay in the existing
order, this time capitalism which, though it had proved itself
eminently capable of producing in abundance the goods necessary
to insure a good life for all, seemed hopelessly at a loss when
it came to distributing them in an equitable manner.
The economic radicals therefore felt, that
they, too, must step outside the established system if they were
to achieve the rapid pace of improvement they desired. The new
system they introduced was socialism.
Transferring the central power of production
from the individual to the state, it now became possible to re-transfer
an increased power of consumption from the state to the individual,
thereby liquidating the last of the circumstances obstructing
the happiness of the individual - the fear and tyranny of poverty.
With this all seems to have been accomplished.
Religious radicalism had liberated man's mind
through the establishment of modern faiths such as Islam, Judaism
or Christianity which should not be confused with the political
organisation of these faiths in the form of church, mosque, or
synagogue.
Political radicalism had liberated his person
by introducing representative liberal democracy.
Economic radicalism has liberated his body
through the establishment of the socialist welfare state. Now
the age of affluence has set in.
As a result, the question posed at the beginning
seems indeed legitimate:
Is socialism a spent force?
And more than that: Is radicalism itself dead?
Is there anything left that it could still achieve? Switch over
from the improvement of the human to that of the social lot?
And, in the process, re-enslave man in the grand manner of Egyptian
kings? With the difference perhaps of putting us to work on traffic
circles instead of Sphinxes? Or sputniks instead of pyramids?
And making us lay down our lives for the glory
of the state or the improvement of future generations who will
bear us no more gratitude than we hold for the past, and who
will justly admire no one except the society-reforming monster
who managed to extract our purposeless sacrifice?
Actually, however, there is a fourth circumstance
threatening the freedom of the individual, a fourth freedom to
be secured, and hence a fourth type of radicalism.
And it is this, not liberalism or socialism,
that is beginning to fight the battle for freedom in our age.
Unlike the others, the fourth threat to freedom
has inadvertently but inescapably emerged as a by- product of
the liberation from the third.
For in order to fulfil its mission of freeing
man from the iniquities of capitalist distribution, socialism
had to increase first the scope, then the function, and finally
the power of the state. And it is the power of the state that
constitutes both the newest and the most terrible threat to freedom.
For as this power increases, the danger rises
that the tool of the citizen's welfare becomes the master of
the citizen; and the pluralist state in which the individual
is sovereign becomes the unitarian state in which the state is
sovereign; that the society of the free turns into the meaningless
self-glorifying concept of the free society of 1984.
Though up to a certain point the interests
of the two are complementary, they become mutually exclusive
when the power of the state assumes such proportions that its
sheer weight begins to obliterate the freedom-serving institutions
which it had previously provided.
The fourth and last form of Radicalism is
therefore no longer directed against capitalist exploitation,
political privilege or religious superstition. Socialists, Liberals,
and Christians have taken care of these. It is directed against
the power of the state, symbolised by the swollen sponge of Parkinsonian
bureaucracy.
Since this is proportionate to the size of
society on which it feeds, it follows that the most modern form
of radicalism, having again to step outside the existing order
to accomplish its ends, must aim at centering social life in
national communities whose size is so reduced as to render excessive
governmental power both impossible and unnecessary. For what
good is the welfare state if its costs of administration become
larger than the benefits it yields?
The new radicals are therefore the decentralisers,
the federalisers, the regionalists, the regional nationalists
(in contrast to the centralizing, expansionist and hence non-radical
nationalistic power megalomaniacs) such as they begin to emerge
in all corners of the world.
We need only to think of the old movement
in such traditionally radical communities as Sicily, Catalonia,
Brittany, Scotland, Wales, or of such newer ones as they have
recently appeared in Nage, Quebec, Tibet, Goa, Somalia and elsewhere.
The freedom they offer to ensure the trinity
of the other freedoms is the freedom from government, not in
the economic sense of laissez faire but in a personal sense.
As Gwynfor Evans, one of the most inspiring
representatives of this new radicalism fighting to protect the
individual from the tyranny of government, writes so succintly
in his programme for an independent Wales:
'The decentralist would limit the power of
the State…In a totalitarian order even the nation may be
swallowed by the State, and this complete inversion of the right
order has not been uncommon in our time. Still more often, in
countries not rigidly totalitarian, we see within the nation
religious, social and economic communities being weakened or
destroyed by State action. This is a very grave loss, for these
communities do much to develop man's personality and to provide
bulwarks against the State 's erosion of individual freedom…The
individual person must therefore be enabled to withstand the
State when it overreaches itself. . . In the Welsh nationalist
view therefore the nation is a community of communities, and
the State fails in its proper function if these communities are
weakened rather than strengthened by it.'
Thus, while socialist radicalism may indeed
have fulfilled its mission, radicalism itself is far from being
dead. Its fourth manifestation is only just beginning.